logo

42 pages 1 hour read

Euripides

Hippolytus

Fiction | Play | Adult | Published in 428

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Themes

The Destructiveness of Love and Desire

Content Warning: This section of the guide contains references to death by suicide.

The destructiveness of love and desire is one of the main themes of Euripides’s Hippolytus, a play that contrasts Phaedra’s inappropriate passion for Hippolytus with Hippolytus’s pursuit of chastity. The play highlights the dangerous and destructive power of love and desire, especially by personifying these forces as the plotting goddess of love, Aphrodite.

At the beginning of the play, Phaedra is represented as the passive and helpless victim of Aphrodite. In the Prologue, Aphrodite herself describes how she caused Phaedra’s heart to be “filled with the longings of dreadful love” (28). When Phaedra first comes on stage, she displays the physical symptoms of love’s devastation: feverish, disheveled, and rambling. She is consumed by her desire for Hippolytus even though she feels bound by societal norms of fidelity to her husband Theseus. Phaedra’s attempts to suppress her feelings have failed. She sees herself as a passive victim of love and the love gods, and this view is confirmed by the way the other characters view and describe love: The Nurse, for instance, refers to Aphrodite as “something stronger than a god” (360), or as a goddess whose “tide […] is not withstandable” (442-43), while the Chorus compares love to “a flitting bee in the world’s garden / and for its flowers destruction is in its breath” (561-62). Sure enough, Phaedra’s inability to control her love leads her to end her life, thus becoming an example of the destructive power of love and desire.

Hippolytus is the play’s other victim of forbidden love. He is a devotee of Artemis and thus has never been sexually active, rejecting any relationships with women. However, the virtuous Hippolytus is really no more temperate than his stepmother: His refusal to have sex or marry means that he cannot produce children, making his lifestyle preemptively “barren” in the sense that it prevents him from producing new life. Indeed, Hippolytus’s hatred of women is taken to an excessive degree: “I’ll hate you women, hate and hate and hate you / and never have enough of hating” (663-64). Even Hippolytus’s death—pursued by a bull and trampled by his panicked horses—can be seen as a symbol of the destructiveness of love when too harshly and intemperately restrained. Hippolytus, like Phaedra, has failed to take to heart the sensible advice spoken by the Nurse early in the play:

The ways of life that are most unbending
trip us up more, they say, than bring us joy.
They’re enemies to health. So I praise less
the extreme than temperance in everything (261-65).

Thus, while the power of love and desire is a dangerous one, it is the intemperance that both Phaedra and Hippolytus exhibit in their respective attitudes toward erotic love that ultimately destroys them.

The Meaning of Honor

There are at least three different approaches to honor represented in the play. Hippolytus, Phaedra, and the Nurse each exemplify their own definition of honor, showing that honor can mean different things to different people and in different social contexts. Far from having a simple meaning in Euripides’s play, honor is shown to be a complex and often conflicting concept.

Hippolytus, regarded by many scholars and critics as the moral paragon of the play, regards honor as an inner quality. For Hippolytus, honor means personal integrity and the pursuit of self-control, duty, and piety. This is an aristocratic approach to honor, prizing the values of the ancient Greek upper classes. Hippolytus takes pride in his devotion to Artemis and his chastity. He values his honor and refuses to compromise his principles, addressing his father with respect and refusing to break his oath even when it means he cannot defend himself against the false accusations of his stepmother Phaedra. Not that Hippolytus is beyond reproach: He boasts that he is “pure and temperate” (1100), but there are sexual overtones lurking behind his devotion to Artemis, and his cruel rejection of Phaedra and misogynistic tirade show that he is far from temperate. These shortcomings notwithstanding, Hippolytus’s approach to honor defines the concept in terms of distinctly aristocratic values.

The Nurse, representing the lower rungs of Greek society, approaches honor very differently. She places her duty to Phaedra above honor, and though she praises traditional values such as temperance, her occasional praise of moral qualities is always purely practical: If it is best to be temperate, it is not because temperance itself is of value, but because those who live an “unbending” (261) lifestyle are more likely to be tripped up. The Nurse dismisses Phaedra’s concerns with her honor as “high moralizing” (490), urging her to act on her feelings for Hippolytus and telling her bluntly that “what you need / is not fine words, but the man!” (490-91). The Nurse feels no scruples about propositioning Hippolytus in Phaedra’s name even when Phaedra forbade her from doing so, and her justification of immoral behavior on a few occasions echoes the moral relativism that had come to be associated with the sophists of Euripides’s day, itinerant teachers whose lessons emphasized rhetoric and persuasion over strict morality.

Phaedra’s approach to honor falls somewhere in the middle. Unlike the Nurse, Phaedra is not amoral, but her approach to honor is more concerned with the appearance of honor than with honor in itself: In contrast to Hippolytus, Phaedra defines honor as a purely external quality, rather than as an inner one. Phaedra knows that her passion for Hippolytus is morally unacceptable, but the reason she resists her desire is because she wants to maintain her reputation. She contemplates ending her life because she “cannot bear that [she] should be discovered / a traitor to [her] husband and [her] children” (420-21), and ultimately does die by suicide to avoid social dishonor. Phaedra’s equation of honor with reputation is ultimately exposed as shallow and hypocritical, spurring Phaedra’s false accusation of the innocent Hippolytus as a way of maintaining her good name.

The Consequences of Divine Intervention

Like many of Euripides’s plays, Hippolytus is much preoccupied with the relationship between gods and mortals. Specifically, the play explores the destructive consequences of divine intervention, as the goddess Aphrodite destroys Hippolytus (as well as Phaedra) to punish him for neglecting her worship.

Aphrodite boasts in her very first lines that she will “lay by the heels” (7) all those who fail to honor her. Aphrodite’s anger does not destroy only Hippolytus. Aphrodite herself admits that Phaedra—who has done nothing to offend Aphrodite—will die too as part of her revenge against Hippolytus:

Renowned shall Phaedra be in her death, but none the less
die she must.
Her suffering shall not weigh in the scale so much
that I should let my enemies go untouched
escaping payment of a retribution
sufficient to satisfy me (47-50).

The death and destruction set in motion by Aphrodite’s intervention does not even end with Phaedra. Theseus will also be left desolate, experiencing the loss of his wife as well as his son. Aphrodite’s machinations will also sow the seeds for further destruction as Artemis vows to avenge Hippolytus by slaying “another mortal, whichever one she loves / the most” (1421-422)—an allusion to the myth that it was Artemis who brought about the death of Aphrodite’s darling Adonis. Thus, the destructive ripples of divine intervention extend far beyond the action of the play.

In the world of the play, all things destructive virtually become synonymous with divinity: If love is destructive, it is because love is a god; if Theseus causes the death of his son by leaping to conclusions, it is because the gods “tripped up” (1414) his judgment or because he has been “blinded by the gods” (1434).

The relationship between gods and mortals is hardly a symmetrical one, though there does exist an element of reciprocity between the powerful gods and their cowed mortal devotees. Aphrodite declares that she honors those who honor her; Artemis claims that “the gods do not rejoice when the pious die; / the wicked we destroy, children, house and all” (1340-341). Hippolytus, who has fervently worshiped Artemis, is granted cult honors by the goddess after his death “by way of compensation for these ills” (1423). Nevertheless, even the good the gods do is tainted with destruction: Poseidon’s response to his son Theseus’s prayer means death for Hippolytus; later, Artemis confesses that she was powerless to stop Aphrodite from hurting Hippolytus even though she knew his fate, and part of the way she honors Hippolytus is by plotting against Aphrodite’s mortal favorite, thus perpetuating the cycle of destruction.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text